Body | Ben, Bernard, Gary, list,
I noticed, somewhat to my surprise, that you are discussing two of my papers on the list. To be honest, I had forgotten that the Collateral Experience paper is on the net; it was a presentation at a local research seminar, and in many respects not polished enough for worldwide distribution. The listeners were not Peirceans, which explains some of the simplifications as well. But I am not trying to avoid your criticism by such feeble excuses; the main substance of the paper (and of the older Communication one) found its way into my dissertation, which as it happens I defended publicly about ten days ago.
The issues you have raised in your critical comments are quite substantial, but perhaps too extensive to be handled in a single mail or even a series of mails. But I want to thank you for paying this much attention to my papers, and will try to address some of your questions and criticisms. I will pick out these from your mails, paste them below, and try to reply in between.
Bernard: --- ...what bothers me with Mats account is that he is using it [emergence of the concept of "collateral experience"] as some trace in favour of the thesis of a change in Peirce's semiotics: -----------------------Quote Mats--------------------------- "Given that Peirce emphasis the role of collateral experience in his later philosophy, one might surmise that he discards his earlier view of the omnipresence of interpretation. Though the distinction between the immediate and the dynamical object, Peirce seems to signal that at least one ASPECT (my emphasis) of the object is of a non-representational nature" (Concluding remarks in the Collateral Experience paper). -------------------------------- There would have to question the de facto equivalence that is stated between interpretation and representation here but I let it aside. This statement is akin to the position of Christopher Hookway in his book Truth, Rationality, and Pragmatism (2000). The idea is that the "late" Peirce is turning more toward reference, indexicality of signs by means of the dynamic object concept. But it seems to me to be a too rough shortcut that tends a) to interpret the dynamical object into a very narrow sense, b) escapes the nature of the relationship between immediate and dynamical object, and c) escapes accounting for the "real" object. ---
MB: You are right in bringing up Hookway in this context; I do tend to sympathise with his account. In my opinion, there is little doubt that certain significant changes occur in Peirce's semiotic thought, and that it is meaningful to speak (roughly) of an earlier and a later period in his theory of signs. I realise that this idea of two periods may be controversial. I may also have over-emphasised the referential function in the Collateral Experience paper; but it was not meant to be a full account of Peirce's object, nor of the immediate-dynamical relation. (I have tried to address these issues somewhat more fully in my dissertation.) My principal aim in the paper was to show that the concept of collateral experience allows Peirce to escape the semiotic hermeticism that seems to plague some of his early statements ("all is representative", 1865; but also the later "sign under sign endlessly", 1905). This requires the recognition that there is something in experience that is not of the nature of a sign. We find several indications that Peirce came to see the matter in this way in his later semiotic thought: "the outward clash", the criticism of the Hegelians, the emphasis on the brute duality of secundan experiences, the developed theory of indexicality, etc. However, after writing the Collateral Experience paper I think I found the most important sign (no pun intended) of change in Peirce's recognition that the percept is _not_ a sign; it is the object of the perceptual judgment. This is most clearly argued in "Telepathy" from 1903 (in CP 7). I further think that there is a relevant parallel between the immediate object and the percipuum, but that is of less importance here. At the same time, I must concede that there are texts in which Peirce seems to treat of the percept as a sign; my solution has been to follow Richard Bernstein, and hold that Peirce is in these cases speaking carelessly, using "percept" where "percipuum" would be preferable. To render this interpretation of mine plausible, it is necessary to recognise that Peirce uses "experience" in a narrow and a broad sense. In the narrow sense, an experience is brute and singular - pure secondness (could be called "singular experience"). In the broad sense, experience is the "cognitive resultant" of our lives, which is never free from the interpretative element - and in that sense of the character of thirdness. In both cases, "experience" retains a strong flavour of secondness as something that is forced upon cognition whether we want it to or not, but singular experiences differ from experiences in the broad sense by being what Peirce in some contexts calls "ultimate realities" (an easily misunderstood concept) - it is the reality of the here and now, "the blow to one's face", rather than the reality of the permanent, continuous, or intelligible.
Somebody - Ben, I think - already raised the question of what you mean by the "real object". I am also puzzled about how you see the matter; is it something distinct from the dynamical object? ---
Bernard: --- Mats is interested into the communicative function of signs, something which is not very developed by Peirce I think. I do think too that it is our specific job today in order to make actual the peircian semiotic system. But this agenda ought to be placed in conformity with the whole system (or its precise critic) as well as its possible continuations. However, in his Communication paper Mats makes to my sense a complete misinterpretation of the famous text about the bricks falling one after the other in attributing to Peirce a conception of the sign as a communication vehicle. An attentive reading of the passage shows that, while Peirce is speaking of a movement's energy passing from a brick to its following, he isn't making communication a matter of dyadic relation. On the contrary the so-called energy isn't mechanical but is a formal cause, a capacity or potential, that is to say an "operation of mind" as he calls it. I think that this point has to be cleared up before going further. ---
MB: I will just briefly say that I have tried to take certain steps the direction you suggested at the beginning of this passage in my dissertation by discussing how Peirce in 1907 "derived" the sign relation from an ordinary dialogical situation. This has been noted before, but I think I managed to unearth some new material of interest and establish at least some suggestive connections. As to the bricks example, I must say I was not aware that this was a widely discussed passage. I would be very interested in seeing what others have made of it, if you have the references. Your criticism seems to focus on the idea of a formal cause; now, it is true that a certain kind of potential is transferred in the bricks example. But let us look at it a bit more carefully. To make this clear to people that do not have the text in question (I do not have it in front of me right now, either, so I hope I get this right), the idea is roughly this: some bricks are lined up so that if one is knocked over in a certain direction, it causes a chain reaction, tipping over the others. Let us say that there are three bricks, A, B, C. A is accidentally tipped over so that B subsequently knocks C down. The question is: is this a full sign relation, a primitive kind of semiosis (triadic action)? In this context, Peirce seems to view the matter thus (the mediating brick B being a sign of the action of the first brick A for the third brick C), and if I understand you correctly Bernard, you would agree. I tend to disagree for the following reasons: (1) Obviously, the bricks are potential signs (as anything whatever is). But they are not actualised (active) as such before they are so interpreted. (2) Of course, this is a triadic relation. However, it is degenerate. Not all triadic relations are signs. (3) If we were to accede that the chain reaction is semiosis, then there would be no meaningful distinction between dyadic and triadic action (the latter being usually characterised by something acting as a means for something). Anything caused by something second thereby causing something third would be an instance of semiosis. But then, everything happening would be semiosis and the concept would lose whatever explanatory and analytical power it may have. (4) The notion of a "formal cause" seems to be quite foreign to Peirce (not entirely, however). I know he has been criticised - by John Deely, for instance - for employing a too limited arsenal of causes, rather than the full Aristotelian set. However, if my argument 3 is on the right track, then the notion of formal cause must be problematic in the context of sign action. Are we prepared to say that the presence of a formal cause is sufficient to render an event an instance of semiosis? Or of mind? This is of course a question of how to draw the borders of the domain of signs and mind. I suppose I should confess colour here; I tend to view attempts to extend semiosis into the inorganic world as highly problematic (I am aware of the fact that Peirce sees the operation of mind in the function of crystals). In the words of T. L. Short, "what's the use"? Perhaps you can enlighten me. Having said this, I think Peirce's c. 1906 example of the bricks could be made compatible with some of his other statements of the period, if we do not see brick B as a sign but rather as a medium (the sign being only one kind of medium of communication, itself a species of medium, which is a species of third - EP 2:390). The brick would be a medium of communication according to Peirce's definition (see EP 2:391), but not necessarily a sign (like a mosquito transmitting a disease). The difficulty I have with this is simply that I would prefer to use "communication" for a more developed form of triadic action; in the case of the bricks, there is a transmission of an effect, but when the event is over, the energies have been exhausted (for that relation). Brick B's capacity to act as a mediator is rather limited; it transfers the effect, and that is it. A sign functions differently - or so I am inclined to see the matter. ---
Ben: --- though Bergman characterize semiotic determination as "delimitation" -- presumably he means delimitation in a different sense; indeed he goes on to say "Put differently, the dynamical object does not determine the sign absolutely, so as to always produce a given interpretant or set of interpretants," which sounds on surer ground to me. ---
MB: Just a quick comment on this. I would say that the minimal requirement for a dynamical object is delimitation; it guides us toward certain interpretations rather than others. Sometimes this is achieved merely by negation, i.e., closing certain paths of interpretation. Usually, however, the dynamical object will also play a more substantial role. Characterising the minimal requirement for a dynamical object as delimitation is - as far as I can see - the only way to argue that all signs have dynamical (or real) objects. The important thing is that the dynamical object is in intention or pretension _not_ created by the sign; it is in that sense "real" _as far as the action of the sign is concerned_. I cannot resist pasting this quote from Peirce here, as I think it will be of interest but is not widely known:
"...the phrase "the real Object of a Sign" does not imply that the Sign is altogether veracious. The word "witch" is a sign having a "real Object" in the sense in which this phrase is used, namely to mean a supposedly real Object, not the Sign, and in intention or pretension not created by the Sign, and consequently professedly real as far as the action of the Sign is concerned. It is real in the sense in which a dream is a real appearance to a person in sleep, although it be not an appearance of objects that are Real." (MS 634:26 [1909])
I would be particularly interested to read Bernard's take on this.
Ben: --- For Peirce, a collateral experience is a kind of index. (Quotation later in post.) I find it difficult to reconcile this with Peirce's emphatic idea that signs do not convey acquaintance, when we have here a collateral experience, a collateral acquaintance, which, as such, is supposed to be a kind of index which, for all its indexicality, is still a sign. (Of course, a collateral experience, like any singular thing, may determine an index, e.g., a memory, which points back to it.) Furthermore, Peirce can't reduce collateral experience to index without leaving its collateral aspect unaccounted for. And indeed we find it continually necessary to distinguish collateral experience from all three of the roles in the semiotic triad of object, sign, interpretant. I just point out that it appears that neither he nor anybody else has reduced support-by-collateral-experience to interpretant, sign, or object within a same given triad even though interpretant, sign, & object convey nothing without collateral experience & though checking, balancing, & supporting by collateral experience give science much of its character. ---
MB: Thank you very much for this comment and the quote, Ben. I had noticed your "tetradic" point of view before, but had not grasped how pertinent it is to this issue. The passage you quote is curious, for there Peirce does indeed state that collateral observation = index. However, it seems to me that the passage is somewhat anomalous, for instance by making icons and indices to be thought-signs (very 1860s...). One question that arises is whether we should not distinguish collateral observation from collateral experience. Peirce does not seem to put forth such a distinction. Instead, Peirce distinguishes three kinds of indicatively effective signs, and mostly holds all of these separate from the relation s that form collateral experience. I think I will be just lazy here, and paste a bit from my dissertation with a longish quote from Peirce: - What, then, are these indices? They are primarily of two kinds: designations, which force the attention of the interpreter to certain existents, and reagents, which are purer indications. "An index represents an object by virtue of its connection with it. It makes no difference whether the connection is natural, or artificial, or merely mental. There is, however, an important distinction between two classes of indices. Namely, some merely stand for things or individual quasi-things with which the interpreting mind is already acquainted, while others may be used to ascertain facts. Of the former class, which may be termed designations, personal, demonstrative, and relative pronouns, proper names, the letters attached to a geometrical figure, and the ordinary letters of algebra are examples. They act to force the attention to the thing intended. Designations are absolutely indispensable both to communication and to thought. No assertion has any meaning unless there is some designation to show whether the universe of reality or what universe of fiction is referred to. The other class of indices may be called reagents. Thus water placed in a vessel with a shaving of camphor thrown upon it will show whether the vessel is clean or not. If I say that I live two and a half miles from Milford, I mean that a rigid bar that would just reach from one line to another upon a certain bar in Westminster, might be successively laid down on the road from my house to Milford, 13200 times, and so laid down on my reader's road would give him a knowledge of the distance between my house and Milford. Thus, the expression "two miles and a half" is, not exactly a reagent, but a description of a reagent. A scream for help is not only intended to force upon the mind the knowledge that help is wanted, but also to force the will to accord it. It is, therefore, a reagent used rhetorically. Just as a designation can denote nothing unless the interpreting mind is already acquainted with the thing it denotes, so a reagent can indicate nothing unless the mind is already acquainted with its connection with the phenomenon it indicates." (CP 8.368 n. 23; cf. MS 1135:7-8 [c. 1897]) Reagents are proper indices, and as such outside of the domain of symbols, although, as Peirce notes, they may be described using symbolic signs. Designations are characteristically indexical signs, but not pure indices. In the 1903 Syllabus, Peirce states that every subject of a proposition is one of three kinds (EP 2:286), namely 1. an index, such as the environment of the interlocutors, or something attracting attention in that environment, for instance a pointing finger; 2. a subindex, such as a proper name or a pronoun; or 3. a precept, a symbolic legisign that describes to the interpreter what is to be done (by the interpreter of somebody else) in order to obtain an index of the individual (whether a unit or a single set of units) and that assigns a designation to that individual. Subindices or designations do not constitute collateral acquaintance, but they force the attention to the relevant experience. In contrast, indices or reagents are closely connected to the situation and context of occurrence, and cannot be properly expressed by words. In the communicative situation, they are whatever in the circumstances of the communication, apart from the verbal utterance itself, enables the identification of the object." - I would formulate the relationship between a reagent and collateral experience as follows: a reagent is a bit of collateral experience (environment, for instance) employed semiotically as an index, but typically based on previous experiences. This is not elegantly put, but I hope it is possible to catch my idea.
---
Ben: --- As signs, indices, like icons & symbols, are Thirds, but indices are "secundan" Thirds. As you point out, Bergman seems to have treated a semeiotic relation as a dyadic relation. Bergman has done it in this case by saying that collateral experience is of the nature of Secondness, rather than saying that it is of the nature of indices in particular. ---
MB: This I do not quite see. What _semiotic_ relation have I treated as dyadic? The index? Where precisely? I indeed hold that collateral experience is primarily of the character of secondness, a position that seems to clash with the passage you quoted but not necessarily with the one I quoted above ("a reagent can indicate nothing unless the mind is already acquainted with its connection with the phenomenon it indicates"). I do agree that it may be wise not to overemphasise the gap between the index and collateral experience; I may have been careless with in this respect. I would say that the index is precisely a sign that is capable of bringing collateral experience within the semiotic sphere. But - and this is my concern - this does _not_ mean that the brute secondness of the experience would thereby be subsumed into the world of thirdness. I think this is precisely Peirces' criticism of the Hegelians and their tendency to "aufhoben" less complex forms of experience, but a trap into which he himself seems to have fallen by asserting that "all is representative" or by the unqualified statements to the effect that the object is always also a sign. Ironically, that path led him occasionally to embrace certain nominalistic views about the object as a "dark underlying something" - a "representationist" stance that he in effect abandoned in some of his writings on perception - or so I would argue. But that is another story...
---
I know I have not by a long shot answered your questions and criticisms, but I think I will stop here for now (need to get some work done on an article). I look forward to your responses.
Best, Mats
|